GMAT考试Testprep数学精解2

雕龙文库 分享 时间: 收藏本文

GMAT考试Testprep数学精解2

  If I eat nuts, then I break out in hives. This in turn can be symbolized as N――H.

  Next, we interpret the clause there is a blemish on my hand to mean hives, which we symbolize as H. Substituting these symbolssintosthe argument yields the following diagram:

  N――H

  H

  Therefore, N

  The diagram clearly shows that this argument has the same structure as the g

  iven argument. The answer, therefore, is 。

  Denying the Premise Fallacy

  A――B

  ~A

  Therefore, ~B

  The fallacy of denying the premise occurs when an if-then statement is prese

  nted, its premise denied, and then its conclusion wrongly negated.

  Example:

  The senator will be reelected only if he opposes the new tax bill. But he wa

  s defeated. So he must have supported the new tax bill.

  The sentence The senator will be reelected only if he opposes the new tax b

  ill contains an embedded if-then statement: If the senator is reelected, then he opposes the new tax bill. This in turn can be symbolized as R――~T. The sentence But the senator was defeated can be reworded as He was not reelected, which in turn can be symbolized as ~R. Finally, the sentence He must have supported the new tax bill can be symbolized as T. Using these symbols the argument can be diagrammed as follows:

  R――~T

  ~R

  Therefore, T

   This diagram clearly shows that the argument is committing the fallacy of denying the premise. An if-then statement is made; its premise is negated; then its conclusion is negated.

  Transitive Property

  A――B

  B――C

  Therefore, A――C

  These arguments are rarely difficult, provided you step back and take a birds-eye view. It may be helpful to view this structure as an inequality in mathematics. For example, 5 4 and 4 3, so 5 3.

  Notice that the conclusion in the transitive property is also an if-then statement. So we dont know that C is true unless we know that A is true. However, if we add the premise A is true to the diagram, then we can conclude that C is true:

  A――B

  B――C

  A

  Therefore, C

  As you may have anticipated, the contrapositive can be generalized to the transitive property:

  A――B

  B――C

  ~C

  Therefore, ~A

  Example:

  If you work hard, you will be successful in America. If you are successful in America, you can lead a life of leisure. So if you work hard in America, you can live a life of leisure.

  Let W stand for you work hard, S stand for you will be successful in America, and L stand for you can lead a life of leisure. Now the first sentence translates as W――S, the second sentence as S――L, and the conclusion as W――L. Combining these symbol statements yields the following diagram:

  W――S

  S――L

  Therefore, W――L

  The diagram clearly displays the transitive property.

  DeMorgans Laws

  ~ = ~A or ~B

  ~ = ~A ~B

  If you have taken a course in logic, you are probably familiar with these formulas. Their validity is intuitively clear: The conjunction AB is false when either, or both, of its parts are false. This is precisely what ~A or ~B says. And the disjunction A or B is false only when both A and B are false,which is precisely what ~A and ~B says.

  You will rarely get an argument whose main structure is based on these rules――they are too mechanical. Nevertheless, DeMorgans laws often help simplify,clarify,or transform parts of an argument. They are also useful with games.

  Example:

  It is not the case that either Bill or Jane is going to the party.

  This argument can be diagrammed as ~, which by the second of DeMorgans laws simplifies to 。 This diagram tells us that neither of them is going to the party.

  A unless B

  ~B――A

  A unless B is a rather complex structure. Though surprisingly we use it with little thought or confusion in our day-to-day speech.

  To see that A unless B is equivalent to ~B――A, consider the following situation:

  Biff is at the beach unless it is raining.

  Given this statement, we know that if it is not raining, then Biff is at the beach. Now if we symbolize Biff is at the beach as B, and it is rainingas R, then the statement can be diagrammed as ~R――B.

  CLASSIFICATION

  In Logic II, we studied deductive arguments. However, the bulk of arguments on the GMAT are inductive. In this section we will classify and study the major types of inductive arguments.

  An argument is deductive if its conclusion necessarily follows from its premises――otherwise it is inductive. In an inductive argument, the author presents the premises as evidence or reasons for the conclusion. The validity of the conclusion depends on how compelling the premises are. Unlike deductive arguments, the conclusion of an inductive argument is never certain. The truth of the conclusion can range from highly likely to highly unlikely. In reasonable arguments, the conclusion is likely. In fallacious arguments, it is improbable. We will study both reasonable and fallacious arguments.

  We will classify the three major types of inductive reasoning――generalization, analogy, and causal――and their associated fallacies.

  Generalization

  Generalization and analogy, which we consider in the next section, are the main tools by which we accumulate knowledge and analyze our world. Many people define generalization as inductive reasoning. In colloquial speech, the phrase to generalize carries a negative connotation. To argue by generalization, however, is neither inherently good nor bad. The relative validity of a generalization depends on both the context of the argument and the likelihood that its conclusion is true. Polling organizations make predictions by generalizing information from a small sample of the population, which hopefully represents the general population. The soundness of their predictions depends on how representative the sample is and on its size. Clearly, the less comprehensive a conclusion is the more likely it is to be true.

  Example:

  During the late seventies when Japan was rapidly expanding its share of the American auto market, GM surveyed owners of GM cars and asked them whether they would be more willing to buy a large, powerful car or a small, economical car. Seventy percent of those who responded said that they would prefer a large car. On the basis of this survey, GM decided to continue building large cars. Yet during the80s, GM lost even more of the market to the Japanese

  

  Which one of the following, if it were determined to be true, would best explain this discrepancy.

   Only 10 percent of those who were polled replied.

   Ford which conducted a similar survey with similar results continued to build large cars and also lost more of their market to the Japanese.

   The surveyed owners who preferred big cars also preferred big homes.

   GM determined that it would be more profitable to make big cars.

   Eighty percent of the owners who wanted big cars and only 40 percent of the owners who wanted small cars replied to the survey.

  The argument generalizes from the survey to the general car-buying population, so the reliability of the projection depends on how representative the sample is. At first glance, choice seems rather good, because 10 percent does not seem large enough. However, political opinion polls are typically based on only .001 percent of the population. More importantly, we dont know what percentage of GM car owners received the survey. Choice simply states that Ford made the same mistake that GM did. Choice is irrelevant. Choice , rather than explaining the discrepancy, gives even more reason for GM to continue making large cars. Finally, choice points out that part of the survey did not represent the entire public, so is the answer.

  Analogy

  To argue by analogy is to claim that because two things are similar in some respects, they will be similar in others. Medical experimentation on animals is predicated on such reasoning. The argument goes like this: the metabolism of pigs, for example, is similar to that of humans, and high doses of saccharine cause cancer in pigs. Therefore, high doses of saccharine probably cause cancer in humans.

  Clearly, the greater the similarity between the two things being compared the stronger the argument will be. Also the less ambitious the conclusion the stronger the argument will be. The argument above would be strengthened by changing probably to may. It can be weakened by pointing out the dissimil arities between pigs and people.

  Example:

  Just as the fishing line becomes too taut, so too the trials and tribulations of life in the city can become so stressful that ones mind can snap.

  Which one of the following most closely parallels the reasoning used in the argument above?

   Just as the bow may be drawn too taut, so too may ones life be wasted pursuing self-gratification.

   Just as a gamblers fortunes change unpredictably, so too do ones career opportunities come unexpectedly.

   Just as a plant can be killed by over watering it, so too can drinking too much water lead to lethargy.

   Just as the engine may race too quickly, so too may life in the fast lane lead to an early death.

   Just as an actor may become stressed before a performance, so too may dwelling on the negative cause depression.

  The argument compares the tautness in a fishing line to the stress of city life; it then concludes that the mind can snap just as the fishing line can.

  So we are looking for an answer-choice that compares two things and draws a conclusion based on their similarity. Notice that we are looking for an argument that uses similar reasoning, but not necessarily similar concepts. In fact, an answer-choice that mentions either tautness or stress will probably be a same-language trap.

  Choice uses the same-language trap――notice too taut. The analogy between a taut bow and self-gratification is weak, if existent. Choice offers a good analogy but no conclusion. Choice offers both a good analogy and a conclusion; however, the conclusion, leads to lethargy, understates the scope of what the analogy implies. Choice offers a strong analogy and a conclusion with the same scope found in the original: the engine blows, the person dies the line snaps, the mind snaps. This is probably the best answer, but still we should check every choice. The last choice, , uses language from the original, stressful, to make its weak analogy more tempting. The best answer, therefore, is 。

  Causal Reasoning

  Of the three types of inductive reasoning we will discuss, causal reasoning is both the weakest and the most prone to fallacy. Nevertheless, it is a useful and common method of thought.

  To argue by causation is to claim that one thing causes another. A causal argument can be either weak or strong depending on the context. For example, to claim that you won the lottery because you saw a shooting star the night before is clearly fallacious. However, most people believe that smoking causes cancer because cancer often strikes those with a history of cigarette use.

  Although the connection between smoking and cancer is virtually certain, as with all inductive arguments it can never be 100 percent certain. Cigarette companies have claimed that there may be a genetic predisposition in some people to both develop cancer and crave nicotine. Although this claim is highly improbable, it is conceivable.

  There are two common fallacies associated with causal reasoning:

  Confusing Correlation with Causation.

  To claim that A caused B merely because A occurred immediately before B is clearly questionable. It may be only coincidental that they occurred together, or something else may have caused them to occur together. For example, the fact that insomnia and lack of appetite often occur together does not mean that one necessarily causes the other. They may both be symptoms of an underlying condition.

  2. Confusing Necessary Conditions with Sufficient Conditions.

  A is necessary for B means B cannot occur without A. A is sufficient for B means A causes B to occur, but B can still occur without A. For example, a small tax base is sufficient to cause a budget deficit, but excessive spending can cause a deficit even with a large tax base. A common fallacy is to assume that a necessary condition is sufficient to cause a situation. For example, to win a modern war it is necessary to have modern, high-tech equipment, but it is not sufficient, as Iraq discovered in the Persian Gulf War.

  SEVEN COMMON FALLACIES

  Contradiction

  A Contradiction is committed when two opposing statements are simultaneously asserted. For example, saying it is raining and it is not raining is a contradiction. Typically, however, the arguer obscures the contradiction to the point that the argument can be quite compelling. Take, for instance, the following argument:

  We cannot know anything, because we intuitively realize that our thoughts are unreliable.

  This argument has an air of reasonableness to it. But intuitively realize means to know. Thus the arguer is in essence saying that we know that we dont know anything. This is self-contradictory.

  Equivocation

  Equivocation is the use of a word in more than one sense during an argument.

  This technique is often used by politicians to leave themselves an out. If someone objects to a particular statement, the politician can simply claim the other meaning.

  Example:

  Individual rights must be championed by the government. It is right for one to believe in God. So government should promote the belief in God.

  In this argument, right is used ambiguously. In the phrase individual rights it is used in the sense of a privilege, whereas in the second sentence right is used to mean proper or moral. The questionable conclusion is possible only if the arguer is allowed to play with the meaning of the critical word right.

  Circular Reasoning

  Circular reasoning involves assuming as a premise that which you are trying to prove. Intuitively, it may seem that no one would fall for such an argument. However, the conclusion may appear to state something additional, or the argument may be so long that the reader may forget that the conclusion was stated as a premise.

  Example:

  The death penalty is appropriate for traitors because it is right to execute those who betray their own country and thereby risk the lives of millions.

  This argument is circular because right means essentially the same thing as appropriate. In effect, the writer is saying that the death penalty is a ppropriate because it is appropriate.